Guglielmo di Conches e il Dragmaticon philosophiae
Abstract
This dissertation about William of Conches and the Dragmaticon Philosophiae is
divided into two sections. The aim of the first section is to reconstruct the life and the
literary works of one of the most important teachers of Chartres of the twelfth century.
The aim of the second section is to analyse his most important work, written between
1146 and 1149, after undergoing a noteworthy process of rethinking, reorganization and
enlargement of his youthful work, called Philosophia, which had been bitterly attacked
by the cistercian monk William of Saint-Thierry, who denounced its serious theological
errors in 1140 or 1141.
The enquiry about the life of William of Conches, to which the first chapter is
dedicated, has produced some interesting results, which seem to open new areas of
research, especially regarding the philosopher’s place of birth (which may not well be
Conches, but Saint-Martin du Tilleul) and the last phase of his life, which could have
ended in England at the court of Henry II (to whom William was tutor during the writing
of the Dragmaticon), or in Paris as magister scholae. The enquiry about the literary
works of William of Conches, to which the second chapter is dedicated, deals with a
detailed presentation of the historiographical debate, that has so far led to the
identification of the works currently attributed to the philosopher.
The first part of the third chapter is devoted to the analysis of the accusations,
with which William of Saint-Thierry attacked the teacher of Chartres in his De erroribus
Guillelmi de Conchis, and to the verification of their legitimacy. The second part instead
is dedicated to the description of the Dragmaticon’ structure and the novelties of this
work with respect to Philosophia, the presentation of the Dragmaticon’ s purpose, thus
the tractatus de substantiis, and the description of the research method used. With respect
to the latter, William of Conches claims to conduct his research philosophice, in
accordance with the typical approach of philosophers, who deal with universals
expressing themselves through rationes necessariae, but when he investigates the
substances of the physical world, he cannot always argue philosophice about them
because of their mutability, and must sometimes argue dialectice, in accordance with the
typical approach of dialecticians, who deal with particulars expressing themselves
through rationes verisimiles.
2
The fourth chapter is devoted to the presentation of William’s definition of
substance as res per se existens and to the description of the species of substance in the
order in which William presents them in the Dragmaticon. After he speaks about God and
the angels expressing himself through rationes necessariae derived from faith, he then
deals with the elements. In the Dragmaticon William defines element as what is first in
the composition and last in the resolution of the body and describes it as a body that is
invisible, imperceptible and unextended per se. The feature of unextention attribuited to
elementary bodies gives them a paradoxical ontological status, as there are no bodies
devoid of the three dimensions of space. But the paradoxicalness of this description stems
from the fact that in the Dragmaticon William describes element from the point of view
of philosophers, who speak about universals expressing themselves through rationes
necessariae. According to philosophers element is a body without dimension, because it
is not a physical being, but a metaphyisical one, that is an abstract form similar to a
geometric point. The philosopher then can only postulate the existence of beings, which
are first in the composition and last in the resolution of the body, but he cannot prove
their existence in re. However, it is from the fact that postulating the existence of simple
and minimal particles of the bodies is more rational than not postulating it, that can stem
the existence in re of these particles.
The fifth chapter is devoted to the distinction between opus creatoris and opus
naturae. God creates simultaneously all elements ex nichilo, mixed in a big body mass, so
as to occupy all the existent room. The following exornatio mundi, which is the correct
and balanced disposition of the elements in the world and the formation of the bodies of
living creatures, concerns nature, a kind of ordering principle inside the elements, which
God uses to produce the same from the same in the world. In the exornatio mundi nature
operates within the concept of the same from the same, when it drives the elements to
their cosmic place. In an already formed world nature operates the same from the same,
when it initiates physiological mechanisms (like generation and formation of bodies,
nutrition, appetition, ritention, digestion, expulsion, growth and sleep) typical of an
organic structure.
The sixth chapter deals with the description of the works of nature in the world
through the analysis of the main macrocosmic phenomena, which take place in the four
elementa mundi.
The seventh chapter is devoted to the description of the operations in the human
body which depend on nature, and of those that do not depend on nature, but on the soul.
3
Some of the operations that depend on the soul (like breathing, sense, imagination and
voluntary motion) are common to animals and men. Some others (like wit, memory,
opinion, reason and intelligence) are common to men and divine spirits. The animal soul
is mortal and develops spontaneously in an organic body, whereas the human soul is a
separate and immortal substance. It’s created directly by God and joins the body without
changing its physical nature and takes its course by means of a very fine airy substance,
that arises from the liver, goes through the heart, where it causes breath, and arrives in the
brain after two refining phases. [edited by Author]